Musicologists and philosophers have wondered about this. Sad music can induce intense emotions, yet the type of sadness evoked by music seems pleasing in its own way. Why? Aristotle famously suggested the idea of catharsis: that by overwhelming us with an undesirable emotion, music (or drama) somehow purges us of it.
But what if, despite their apparent similarity, sadness in the realm of artistic appreciation is not the same thing as sadness in everyday life?
In a study published this summer in the journal, Frontiers In Psychology, my colleagues and I explored the idea that "musical emotion" encompasses both the felt emotion that the music induces in the listener and the perceived emotion that the listener judges the music to express. By isolating these two overlapping sets of emotions and observing how they related to each other, we hoped to gain a better understanding of sad music.
Forty-four people served as participants in our experiment. We asked them to listen to one of three musical excerpts of approximately 30 seconds each. The excerpts were from Mikhail Glinka's La Separation (F minor), Felix Blumenfeld's Sur Mer (G minor) and Enrique Granados' Allegro de Concierto (C sharp major, though the excerpt was in G major, which we transposed to G minor).
We were interested in the minor key because it is canonically associated with sad music, and we steered clear of well-known compositions to avoid interference from any personal memories related to the pieces.
(Our participants were more or less split between men and women, as well as between musicians and non-musicians, though these divisions turned out to be immaterial.)
A participant would listen to an excerpt and then answer a question about his felt emotions: "How did you feel when listening to this music?" Then he would listen to a "happy" version of the excerpt - that is, transposed into the major key - and answer the same question.
Next he would listen to the excerpt, again in both sad and happy versions, each time answering a question about other listeners that was designed to elicit perceived emotion: "How would normal people feel when listening to this music?"
(This is a simplification: In the actual study, the order in which the participant answered questions about felt and perceived emotion, and listened to sad and happy excerpts, varied from participant to participant.)
Our participants answered each question by rating 62 emotion-related descriptive words and phrases - from happy to sad, from bouncy to solemn, from heroic to wistful - on a scale from 0 (not at all) to four (very much).
We found, as anticipated, that felt emotion did not correspond exactly to perceived emotion. Although the sad music was both perceived and felt as "tragic" (gloomy, meditative and miserable), the listeners did not actually feel the tragic emotion as much as they perceived it. Likewise, when listening to sad music, the listeners felt more "romantic" emotion (for example, fascinated and in love) and "blithe" emotion (for example, merry and animated) than they perceived.
Something similar happened with the happy music: Perceived blithe emotions were rated higher than their felt counterparts. In general, it appears that perceived emotions may be rated higher than felt emotions when it comes to emotional categories characteristically associated with a given key.
When listening to sad music, then, there is a tension, or slippage, between the two types of emotions. How are we to understand this gap?
One answer may be that in everyday life we typically experience emotions that have a direct connection to whatever object or situation gives rise to them. But when we listen to sad music (or watch a sad movie, or read a sad novel), we are inoculated from any real threat or danger that the music (or movie or novel) represents.
If this is true, what we experience when we listen to sad music may be thought of as "vicarious emotions". Here, there is no object or situation that induces emotion directly, as in regular life. Instead, the vicarious emotions are free from the essential unpleasantness of their genuine counterparts, while still drawing force from the similarity between the two.
We need to study vicarious emotions further. In doing so, we may be able to improve our understanding of a neglected feature of our emotional system - namely, its sensitivity to something other than palpable needs or threats. When we weep at the beauty of sad music, we experience a profound aspect of our emotional selves that may contain insights about the meaning and significance of artistic experience - and also about ourselves as human beings.
NEW YORK TIMES
The writer is a post-doctoral fellow with the Okanoya Emotional Information Project of the Japan Science and Technology Agency.